{"id":9015,"date":"2011-10-21T16:26:51","date_gmt":"2011-10-21T20:26:51","guid":{"rendered":"http:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/?p=9015"},"modified":"2012-12-26T16:08:04","modified_gmt":"2012-12-26T21:08:04","slug":"examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt","status":"publish","type":"post","link":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/","title":{"rendered":"Examining The Legacy Of Tony Judt"},"content":{"rendered":"

The Article:<\/strong> Tony Judt: A Cooler Look<\/a> by Dylan Riley in the New Left Review.<\/p>\n

The Text:<\/strong> Accolades continue to be piled upon the historian Tony Judt, following his untimely death in August 2010. For the Guardian, he was \u2018a fearless critic of narrow orthodoxies\u2019, \u2018a great historian\u2019, \u2018a brilliant political commentator\u2019. For the New York Review of Books, \u2018a source of inspiration\u2019, who sought to \u2018embrace difference\u2019\u2014\u2018like Isaiah Berlin\u2019\u2014within historical accounts that were \u2018harmonious, convincing, and true\u2019; like Camus, Blum and Aron, Judt knew what it was to bear the intellectual\u2019s \u2018burden of responsibility\u2019. To the Economist, he was \u2018erudite and far-sighted\u2019, \u2018a meticulous intellect\u2019\u2014\u2018an intellectual with a capital I\u2019. More circumspectly, the New York Times saluted his \u2018deep suspicion of left-wing ideologues\u2019. In June 2011 a Paris conference, jointly organized by the NYRB and ceri SciencesPo, celebrated Judt\u2019s \u2018scholarly rigour, elegance of style and acuteness of judgement\u2019. Morally, he was \u2018fearless\u2019, \u2018prophetic\u2019, a new Orwell; intellectually, he was \u2018formidable\u2019, possessed of a \u2018forceful lucidity\u2019; as a historian of French political life, happily \u2018inoculated against the revolutionary ideas that had been the stock in trade of the intellectual engag\u00e9\u2019. To what extent are these plaudits confirmed by a sober examination of Judt\u2019s work, held to the normal scholarly standards of intellectual coherence and empirical plausibility? What follows will offer an evaluation of his writings, as the necessary precondition for an adequate assessment of his contribution as historian, publicist and scholar.<\/p>\n

Tony Judt was born in 1948, the son of Jewish immigrants, and brought up in lower-middle-class circumstances in London\u2019s south-west suburbs. \u2018Coming from that branch of East European Jewry that had embraced social democracy\u2019, he would explain, \u2018my own family was viscerally anti-Communist.\u2019 Educated at a small South London private school, he served as national secretary of a Labour Zionist youth organization before going up to King\u2019s College, Cambridge in 1967. Post-graduate study took him to the Ecole Normale Sup\u00e9rieure in Paris, where he seems to have acquired his life-long distaste for Marxist intellectuals; and thence to southern France, where he undertook doctoral research on the history of French socialism in the Var. His first two books would draw extensively on this work: La Reconstruction du Parti Socialiste, 1921\u20131926 was published in Paris in 1976; Socialism in Provence, 1871\u20131914, a \u2018study in the origins of the French left\u2019, appeared three years later. The mid-70s was a time of heightened establishment concern in France at the prospect of a joint Socialist\u2013PCF election victory, in the aftermath of the Portuguese revolution. This background informs the central preoccupation in both Judt\u2019s books with why France had failed to produce a reliable social-democratic party, on the Anglo-Nordic model. Unlike its solidly anti-Communist counterparts, the British Labour Party or German sdp, the Section Fran\u00e7aise de l\u2019Internationale Ouvri\u00e8re (SFIO) had never quite shed the lexicon of Marxism and still appealed to a notion of socialism even after 1945, when its political practice was otherwise quite \u2018acceptable\u2019. The themes of his doctoral research would prove to be central to much of Judt\u2019s subsequent career.<\/p>\n

1. THE FRENCH LEFT<\/strong><\/p>\n

Judt\u2019s first book, The Reconstruction of the Socialist Party, examined the re-establishment of the SFIO after its historic split at the 1920 Congress of Tours, where a large majority of the delegates had opted for the Third International and moved to found the Parti Communiste Fran\u00e7aise. In Judt\u2019s view, it was the presence of a militant PCF to its left that forced the SFIO leadership to compensate for its reformist political practice with verbal commitments to socialism. The SFIO rank and file insisted that the party \u2018remain what they had made it\u2019; any attempts to dilute its message would have played into the hands of the PCF. As Judt put it:<\/p>\n

The way was narrow: a too marked rapprochement with the PCF could allow the more radical and rigid party to destroy it, but too sharp a break from the communists could lead to the loss of elements who had remained in the SFIO only on the condition that it retained a revolutionary Marxist position.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

The 1920 split had not cleanly separated reformists from revolutionaries, as happened in other northern European socialist parties after the Bolshevik Revolution; instead, a section of the left remained with the rump SFIO led by L\u00e9on Blum, constituting a majority of its membership. Apart from a small, right-wing faction, all the SFIO delegates rejected collaboration in bourgeois governments and advocated the dictatorship of the proletariat. Judt reported that Socialist mayors were obliged to get party approval before inaugurating Monuments to the Fallen, a sharply divisive issue for the party in the aftermath of the Great War. The SFIO leadership initially hung back from rejoining the reconstituted Second International, preferring to support the Union of Vienna, the \u20182.5 International\u2019 established by the Austro-Marxists, although it duly signed up in 1923. Rank-and-file attitudes exercised a decisive restraint on the SFIO\u2019s parliamentary leadership: in 1924 Blum and his fellow deputies were obliged to lend only external support to the Radical government under Edouard Herriot\u2014as it pursued a programme of austerity at home, imperial war in Morocco and military occupation in the Ruhr\u2014since the party membership would not tolerate full participation. Here was an example of the high price paid by the SFIO for the ideological \u2018rigidity\u2019 necessary for its survival, given the ever-present pressure from the left exercised by the PCF.<\/p>\n

<\/p>\n

The Reconstruction of the Socialist Party was rapturously received in liberal-Atlanticist circles in France, where it was published by the National Political Science Foundation with a fulsome preface by the ex-Communist Annie Kriegel, whom even Judt was later to describe as having gone from \u2018full-blooded party dogma to conservative anti-Communism\u2019. Its warnings of the baneful effect of the PCF had obvious lessons for those tempted by the Union of the Left in the mid-70s. Anti-Communism had been the standard ideology in the Anglophone world all through the Cold War; but in France it only really became a doxa in the mid-70s. Solzhenitsyn\u2019s Gulag Archipelago was translated in 1974 and Fran\u00e7ois Furet\u2019s influential Rethinking the French Revolution was published in 1978. In this context, Judt\u2019s hostile account of the PCF\u2019s influence in the 1920s was the perfect calling card; a long-existent Anglo-American anti-Communism converged felicitously with a rising French one.<\/p>\n

Judt\u2019s second book, Socialism in Provence, 1871\u20131914, tracked back to a time before the baneful influence of the Comintern had been felt, aiming to rescue a vision of the modern French left as \u2018neither a victime du marxisme nor the latest in a succession of crypto-Jacobins\u2019. Drawing again on his doctoral research in the Var, Judt argued that the areas of late-nineteenth-century Socialist success were districts where small peasant proprietors were predominant, rather than sharecroppers or day labourers. The collapse of agricultural prices in the last decades of the nineteenth century had radicalized this layer. Picking up on Eric Wolf\u2019s idea of the \u2018middle peasant\u2019, Judt suggested that their relative economic autonomy gave small proprietors the capacity for independent action, while their vulnerability to market conjunctures, especially after the turn to viniculture, made them supporters of state protection for agriculture. Early Socialist programmes spoke directly to smallholder interests; initially, the Var peasants were \u2018responding to an ideology which appealed to them in class terms\u2019 in lending the party their support. Subsequently, this attachment would congeal into an unbreakable political tradition: \u2018voting for the Socialists formed part of the \u201chistorical\u201d character of Proven\u00e7al life, long after the SFIO had ceased to perform any obvious function on behalf of the local population and had indeed lost much of its revolutionary character and programme.\u2019 In sum, material interests explained the rise of socialism, culture its perdurance.<\/p>\n

As a work of empirical scholarship Socialism in Provence towers over Judt\u2019s later output, its extensively documented analysis revealing a careful social historian. The last chapters turn towards a more general discussion of French politics and the peasantry. Judt\u2019s argument here is a familiar one: the persistence of a broadly Marxian socialism in France was due to the large number of peasant smallholders, combined with the early introduction of universal suffrage: both legacies of the French Revolution. France\u2019s backwardness, far from being a disadvantage for socialism in France, explained why it had done so relatively well. Judt gave a nod to modernization theory, agreeing that \u2018the potential for revolution\u2019 is greatest \u2018in the early years of capitalist development\u2019. But its explanation was limited in the French case, because socialism did not disappear as the country modernized. Overall, however, the story was clear: French socialism rested above all on a peasant base, and as such was a consequence of economic backwardness.<\/p>\n

In Furet\u2019s footsteps<\/strong><\/p>\n

In an unguarded moment, Judt himself would remark that \u2018at some point between 1973 and 1978 Marxism, and the study of its theoretical implications and resonances, lost its stranglehold upon the intellectual imagination in France, a grip it had exercised unbroken for a generation. In the space of less than a decade it became fashionable to be not just non-Marxist, but anti-Marxist.\u2019 Indeed; both his early works chimed perfectly with the dominant Parisian mood. Judt\u2019s next book\u2014he was ensconced, from 1980 to 1987, at St. Anne\u2019s College, Oxford as a ppe tutor\u2014was also well-angled to catch this favourable wind. Published in 1986, Marxism and the French Left was Judt\u2019s first foray into intellectual history. It had an unusual structure, to say the least: dense chapters on the nineteenth-century labour movement and the fortunes of the SFIO from 1920\u201336 were followed by a highly polemical presentation of French Marxism during the trente glorieuses of 1945\u201375, topped off by a paean to Mitterrand\u2019s victory in 1981.<\/p>\n

Linking these apparently disparate topics is a highly selective narrative of the French left, occluding the anti-Nazi Resistance\u2014indeed, dispensing with any analysis of the PCF. An ostentatiously partisan tone and a marked decline in scholarship set Marxism and the French Left apart from Judt\u2019s earlier work; it also suffered from a notable deterioration in internal coherence, as Judt attempted to put forward two mutually contradictory arguments in the same breath. On the one hand Marxism and the French Left claimed, following Furet, that the French left had historically been blighted by an adherence to \u2018revolutionary doctrines\u2019, with little countervailing experience of Anglo-Saxon liberties. During the course of the nineteenth century, post-1789 republican traditions had segued into Marxian ones, facilitated by the overlap of the two between the 1860s and the 1930s. On the other hand, Judt informed his readers that it was only after 1945 that \u2018consistently critical attitudes to capitalism\u2019 had taken hold on the French left, though mercifully \u2018their hegemony has been brief; in the 1980s it is again no longer a requirement of the left that it condemn profit, economic exploitation and wealth\u2019, as Mitterrand\u2019s presidency had shown.<\/p>\n

The explanation that Judt had confidently offered for the persistence of the revolutionary tradition in his earlier works is\u2014just as confidently\u2014reversed, without a word of explanation, in Marxism and the French Left. In 1979 Socialism in Provence had depicted nineteenth-century France as an economically backward society, with a precociously developed state. In 1986 Marxism and the French Left presented it as an economically developed society with a backward, \u2018illiberal\u2019 state:<\/p>\n

France was an industrial society with all the characteristic industrial landscaping\u2014massive conurbations (Lille-Roubaix-Tourcoing, St Etienne), fast-growing metropolitan cities (Paris, of course, but also Marseilles, which grew from 185,000 to 315,000 during Louis Napol\u00e9on\u2019s reign), gross extremes of wealth and poverty.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

In promoting mid-nineteenth-century France to the rank of a fully industrialized society, Judt directly contradicted his previous account of the strength of French socialism being due to its anchorage in pre-industrial soil. Without ever mentioning this, he now offered a new explanation for the persistence of the revolutionary tradition: the repressiveness of the Second Empire. After the massacre of the workers in 1848, the French labour movement no longer saw the state as a neutral arbiter of class conflicts but rather as an instrument that \u2018would always be used at the expense of the working population\u2019. The French, then, had never experienced \u2018that political liberalization which so confounded observers and protagonists after 1848 in other countries.\u2019<\/p>\n

The chapter on the inter-war experience of the SFIO in Marxism and the French Left similarly recasts, without explanation, Judt\u2019s earlier analysis in Reconstruction of the Socialist Party. Even after the split at the Congress of Tours, in which the PCF hived off most of the industrial working-class members, leaving the SFIO as a cross-class, regional party, Socialist leaders continued to stress extra-parliamentary agitation: \u2018for Blum, almost as much as for the party left, elections were a means to spread the socialist word, and only secondarily did they serve to elect men to parliament, or even a local council\u2019. Whereas Judt earlier suggested that the reasons for the SFIO\u2019s failure to become a responsible social-democratic party lay in the existence of the PCF, he now argued that both the SFIO and the PCF were rooted in a common political culture, tainted by \u2018revolutionary doctrine\u2019\u2014much more in line with Furet\u2019s thinking.<\/p>\n

Marxism and the French Left\u2019s discussion of the post-war intellectual scene\u2014Judt\u2019s first stab at Sartre\u2014was strangely sandwiched between this chapter on the SFIO and another on Mitterrand. It asked why it was that French Marxism, backward in comparison to its German and Italian counterparts up until the 1930s, had flowered in the post-war period and then collapsed. According to Judt, this arc reflected the political strength of the PCF, whose attraction for the intelligentsia simply reflected the prestige of Stalin. \u2018As a theory of radical politics\u2019, he declared, \u2018Marxism died with Stalin\u2019. The argument fails the elementary test of chronology: the two greatest products of post-war French Marxism, Sartre\u2019s Critique of Dialectical Reason and Althusser\u2019s Reading Capital, were published in 1960 and 1968, respectively. As intellectual history, this was crude and shoddy stuff, not least because of Judt\u2019s relentlessly polemical intent\u2014Communism, Marxism and Stalinism predictably presented as interchangeable terms. Judt made no attempt to reconstruct the ideas of post-war French thinkers, instead flaunting the fact that he had been \u2018selective\u2019 in his treatment and that his approach had been to deny them any \u2018intellectual autonomy\u2019; why should anyone take Sartre, for example, \u2018very seriously\u2019? With protocols like this, it is not surprising that Judt\u2019s account was not only littered with Cold War grotesqueries\u2014Sartre and Beauvoir making a \u2018daily contribution\u2019 to \u2018the enslavement of the satellite states\u2019\u2014but with extraordinary philological howlers: Althusser, radical critic of Hegel, transmogrified into a \u2018passionate Hegelian\u2019; R\u00e9gis Debray labelled a fellow-thinker of L\u00e9vy and Glucksmann as a theorist of \u2018totalitarianism\u2019, rather than famously contemptuous of both the nouveaux philosophes and their theories.<\/p>\n

Marxism and the French Left had, of course, a happy ending. Judt waxed lyrical about what he called Mitterrand\u2019s \u2018electoral revolution of 1981\u2019: after more than a century, French politics had finally been normalized. The new Parti Socialiste had broken out of its class, regional and religious ghettos; now a responsible reformist force, its only remaining task was to \u2018acquire the political culture of a party of government\u2019 like the Swedish or Austrian social democrats. Mitterrand\u2019s victory was \u2018a major turning point in French political history, of qualitatively greater significance than any hitherto\u2019\u2014\u2018for the Socialists, 1981 was their finest hour\u2019. Not only had Mitterrand and his party \u2018transformed national politics in France\u2019, but they had firmly dissociated the left from \u2018internationalism and anti-militarism\u2019 and could now be trusted on \u2018defence\u2019.<\/p>\n

The French historian<\/strong><\/p>\n

Judt\u2019s first cycle of work, focused on France, comes to a close with Marxism and the French Left. How should it be assessed? Historiographically, the argument of Socialism in Provence is obviously superior to its successor. France\u2019s industrialization was relatively slow in the nineteenth century; it had a large artisan and peasant sector\u2014still almost half the population in 1945; yet it had introduced effective male suffrage as early as 1848. But such an account, linking political consciousness to class structure, raised a problem for Judt: it was too Marxian. Indeed his discomfort with it was clear even in Socialism in Provence where, after carefully establishing the link between peasants\u2019 economic interests and the emergence of socialism, he abruptly abandoned it, without theoretical or empirical motivation, to embrace a cultural explanation for the movement\u2019s continuing appeal. Whatever the risk of conceptual incoherence, the switch was effective as a sort of historiographical cordon sanitaire, insulating twentieth-century France from class analysis.<\/p>\n

Even hedged and sterilized, however, Socialism in Provence\u2019s attempt to link politics to class interests was beyond the pale in the mid-1980s, when Furet and his followers had entirely hegemonized the field. It was this, rather than any underlying intellectual problem, that surely explained Judt\u2019s tacitly revised interpretation in Marxism and the French Left, so dramatically at odds with his first. Yet the central premise on which this new version rested, that late-nineteenth century France was a politically backward society, is patently false. Judt attempted to assimilate the French, Italian, and Spanish states of the period into the same type, but this did serious violence to their respective political histories. Universal male suffrage, for example, did not come to Italy until 1912, or Spain until 1931; it was definitively established in France by the 1880s. More importantly, France had created national representative institutions by the end of the eighteenth century, unlike any other large state on the European continent.<\/p>\n

If Judt failed to provide a compelling historiographical explanation for the appeal of Marxism to a significant layer of French workers, peasants and intellectuals, what of his second argument: that its soft spot for marxisant precepts was responsible for the French left\u2019s lack of political success for most of the twentieth century? The issues here are complex, and Judt\u2019s thinking far from consistent. Clarity requires first defining what \u2018success\u2019 means. For Judt this was obvious enough: a \u2018normal\u2019 social democracy. But it is unclear from a strictly historical point of view why this should be the standard. Judt\u2019s doctoral thesis exemplifies the problem. One of the strengths of Reconstruction of the Socialist Party was its documentation of the broad ideological commitment to revolutionary socialism within the SFIO; Blum himself in the 1920s held that an \u2018impersonal dictatorship of the proletariat\u2019 was an absolute necessity. But in that case, the historical question is not: why did the SFIO fail to act as a reformist social-democratic party, but rather: why did the SFIO fail to live up to its own self-understanding and act as a revolutionary party? Judt had evidently registered this problem in his first book, admitting that, in the 1920s, a programme of revolutionary transformation \u2018did not lack plausibility\u2019; but he characteristically dismissed this line of thinking, on the grounds that even to ask such questions would be to apply a \u2018logical\u2019 rather than a historical standard.<\/p>\n

Historiographically, of course, the reverse is the case: Judt himself was applying an abstracted \u2018logical\u2019 standard, in judging the inter-war SFIO from the perspective of post-war social democracy.<\/p>\n

The political d\u00e9nouement of Judt\u2019s decade-long engagement with the history of the French left was his celebration of the Mitterrand era. But here too his analysis proved dud. According to his\u2014albeit self-contradictory\u2014arguments, the \u2018normalization\u2019 of French politics in the 1980s, with Mitterrand\u2019s victory and the elimination of the PCF as an electoral force, should have led at last to an effective social democracy. In fact, of course, Mitterrand\u2019s legacy was the introduction of a gallicized Thatcherite neo-liberalism and, after 1990, abandonment of the last vestiges of Gaullist foreign policy for full participation in the new Atlantic order. Yet if Judt\u2019s labours in the vineyard of French history produced decreasing historiographical or analytical rewards, his exposure to the methods of Furet and his disciples played a critical role in expanding his repertoire as a pro-Western polemicist. Handily, he would find in the \u2018ethical turn\u2019 fashionable in late Cold War Paris a rhetorical stance and sententious tone that married perfectly with anti-Communist sermonizing. So, in Marxism and the French Left he explained:<\/p>\n

To be a socialist today is to find oneself in one of two positions. On the one hand, you can be in favour of a generalized moral project which asserts itself in conscious defiance of capitalist (interest-related) priorities. Or else you must argue from a series of premises, stated or otherwise, which are still best characterized as \u2018marxism\u2019, and which entail firm commitment to certain propositions about the life span and self-destructive properties of capitalism.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

Judt went on to lament: \u2018it is the unwillingness of most socialists in France to think of themselves as engaged in a project of an essentially indeterminate and partial kind that prevents them adopting the first of the two approaches.\u2019 The second\u2014any theory of capitalism as a system with its own laws of motion\u2014led, he asserted, straight to Soviet-style totalitarian Communism.<\/p>\n

2. MANHATTAN<\/strong><\/p>\n

In the late 1980s, apparently bored by French history (and by his wife), Judt followed the trail blazed by Timothy Garton Ash and numerous others to Eastern Europe. Gorbachev\u2019s diplomacy had removed any obstacles to humanitarian tourism and the region was now thoroughly penetrated by missionaries from the EEC and IMF\u2013World Bank. A crash course in Czech, and meetings with Michnik, Havel and Kis, equipped Judt to present his credentials to Washington in the form of a paper given at the Wilson Center in 1987, \u2018The Politics of Impotence?\u2019. From the vantage point of 2009, Judt would explain Czechoslovakia as his Mitteleuropa destination of choice in terms of its edgier national-cultural stereotype: \u2018that distinctly Polish (or Russian) sense of cultural grandeur was precisely what I wanted to circumnavigate, preferring the distinctively Czech qualities of doubt, cultural insecurity, and sceptical self-mockery.\u2019 At the time, however, his justification had been exactly the opposite: for Czechoslovakians, Judt suggested in 1987, \u2018the whole point of intellectual production is to bear moral witness\u2019. Freed\u2014as the interrogative ironization of the title tried to indicate\u2014from any concrete political engagement by the force of circumstance, intellectuals like Havel answered to a higher \u2018moral responsibility\u2019, just as Judt had told French socialists to do. \u2018The Politics of Impotence?\u2019 reported that, since 1968, oppositional Marxism in Eastern Europe had been replaced by a healthy focus on \u2018rights\u2019. Nevertheless, it warned, \u2018to the extent that socialism is associated with a variety of welfare provisions, social-security systems and guarantees, a \u201creturn\u201d to capitalism would not be regarded with favour by most people.\u2019<\/p>\n

Judt\u2019s re-location to the French Institute at New York University took place the same year, 1987. Shortly after, he scooped a $20 million bequest from the 80-year-old Manhattan socialite and former Ziegfeld Follies star Paulette Goddard, who had accumulated a fortune in the course of several marriages (Charlie Chaplin, Burgess \u2018The Penguin\u2019 Meredith, Erich Maria Remarque). NYU\u2019s Remarque Institute would open its doors in the late 90s, under Judt\u2019s direction. In the meantime, he produced a further reworking of his thoughts on post-war French intellectuals: published in 1993, Past Imperfect: French Intellectuals, 1944\u20131956 was coolly received by specialist scholars but garnered fawning reviews for the director of the Remarque Institute in the key power-and-prestige outlets of the American academy; it also won Judt his first commission from the New York Review of Books.<\/p>\n

To return once again to the subject of the post-war rive gauche might appear to have been flogging a dead horse, especially now that the Cold War had ended. But Judt seems to have felt that Marxism and the French Left had dealt with Sartre and his contemporaries too much in terms of French politics. Now\u2014and with little further reading required\u2014he would lambast their record in the larger global struggle of freedom against Communism, at greater length and brandishing loftier, if still ill-defined, concepts: justice, responsibility, morality and ethics. The Berlin Wall had fallen, but it still remained to extirpate any lingering trace of left-wing ideas. In France, a rabid anti-Sartrean literature had been accumulating since the late 1970s but little of it had yet appeared in English. Casting himself as a courageous moralist, Judt recycled its tropes\u2014principally, that Sartre and Beauvoir were Stalinist apologists\u2014rejecting any mere \u2018neutral historicist account\u2019: \u2018In seeking to explain something that is intrinsically unattractive, to which the reader would normally respond with distaste, one is not excused from the obligation to be accurate, but neither is one under a compelling obligation to pretend neutrality.\u2019<\/p>\n

Here, still more openly than in his previous work, Judt spurned any serious discussion of his subjects\u2019 thought: \u2018This book is neither a history of ideas nor a social history of French intellectuals\u2019; it is about \u2018the marked absence of a concern with public ethics or political morality\u2019 in France\u2014which Judt quickly interpreted, before the reader had time to murmur Les mains sales, as: \u2018why the French response to totalitarianism differed from that of intellectuals elsewhere\u2019. Although presented as an exercise in \u2018a peculiarly Anglo-Saxon tradition of intellectual history\u2019, the result had nothing to do with the Cambridge School; it was more like a posthumous contribution to the literature of the Congress for Cultural Freedom. Judt proceeded chiefly by undocumented assertion, anonymous attribution or conjunctive assimilation\u2014typically: \u2018How, in the face of all this evidence, could intelligent people wilfully defend communism as the hope of the future and Stalin as the solution to the riddle of History?\u2019\u2014as though any thorough-going critic of capitalism was also necessarily a worshiper of Stalin.<\/p>\n

Sartre\u2019s actual record on the Soviet Union\u2014the criticisms of Stalinism in What is Literature, the excoriation of the camps and of the invasion of Hungary in Les Temps modernes\u2014is simply scanted. \u2018Sartre\u2019s philosophical thought during the 30s and early 40s was quite devoid of political and social implications\u2019, writes Judt\u2014the War Diaries? Being and Nothingness? \u2018Sartre\u2019s contemporary opinions precluded any attention to questions of ethics or morality\u2019\u2014Saint Genet? Notebooks for an Ethics? The French radical tradition was \u2018dominated by a combination of republican premises and Marxist projections, conflating the capacities of the state and the interests of the individual\u2019\u2014but wasn\u2019t Existentialism founded on the idea of radical individual freedom? \u2018One very special characteristic of the French style of thought has been the emphasis upon \u201ctotality\u201d, or the absolute\u2019\u2014unlike the Germans? There is a Gallic \u2018distaste for intellectual doubt, uncertainty or scepticism\u2019\u2014Descartes?<\/p>\n

Past Imperfect\u2019s main argument, tirelessly reiterated, was that French left-wing intellectuals in this period lacked \u2018any common ideal of justice\u2019\u2014although Judt also remarked at one point that there was no \u2018consensus about justice\u2019 in France as a whole, either; and indeed offered no conceptualization of his own. The result of this moral vacuum, he concluded, was to undermine French liberalism itself:<\/p>\n

What was missing, then, in the political language of contemporary France were the central premises, the building blocks of a liberal political vision . . . Quite absent was the liberal assumption of a necessary and desirable space between the individual and the collective, the private and the public, society and the state.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

By any measure Tocqueville, Constant and Guizot would appear rather substantial French liberal \u2018building blocks\u2019, constituting a richer tradition than that of nineteenth-century Britain, which produced little more than Mill. But it was the absence of a liberal \u2018political vision\u2019, not a theoretical tradition, that Judt was lamenting. Like the French left, liberalism in the Hexagon had also unfortunately \u2018historicized\u2019 the moral idea of rights, by relating them to 1789. In sum, French liberals failed to grasp that liberalism is \u2018not about some sort of liberal project for society: it is about a society in which the messiness and openness of politics precludes the application of large-scale projects, however rational and ideal.\u2019 The \u2018generalized moral project\u2019 that Judt had extolled seven years before, in Marxism and the French Left\u2014\u2018a project of an essentially indeterminate and partial kind\u2019\u2014was unceremoniously abandoned in Past Imperfect. Projects were now out; only the moral \u2018vision\u2019 was now of value. (Indeed Judt appeared at this stage to have abandoned social democracy as well, preferring to speak of a more inclusive \u2018liberalism\u2019.)<\/p>\n

The intellectual configuration in France in the early 1990s was, of course, the very opposite of Judt\u2019s representation of it. The liberalism of Furet and company was unquestionably the hegemonic ideology of the period. In a ludicrous inversion, Judt depicted it as the lonely, marginal thinking of a tiny minority, allowing him to offer his own thoroughly conventional book as a\u2014tacitly, brave\u2014contribution to heterodoxy, along with theirs. But politically, Past Imperfect suggested that, just as, even after Mitterrand, French social democracy could never quite come up to British or Nordic standards, so French liberals were \u2018unable to commit themselves to the utilitarian or ethical individualism of their British contemporaries\u2019 in the nineteenth century, and even today \u2018few thinkers in France have so far undertaken to construct a moral vocabulary for liberal politics, an ethics, so to speak, of democracy.\u2019 Even with the PCF banished to the fringes, France remained insufficiently Anglo-Saxon.<\/p>\n

Pantheon<\/strong><\/p>\n

Judt\u2019s next book returned to the subject of French intellectuals, this time focused not on his villains, but on his heroes. The Burden of Responsibility: Blum, Camus, Aron and the French Twentieth Century appeared in 1998, dedicated, appropriately enough, to the memory of Fran\u00e7ois Furet. Once again, Judt paid little attention to his subjects\u2019 ideas: according to Burden of Responsibility, Blum made no contribution to socialist theory, Camus was unpolitical, Aron overvalued philosophy. Judt explained that this was a study of political \u2018responsibility\u2019, in contrast to the analysis of political \u2018irresponsibility\u2019 in his previous book. His three exemplars, Blum, Camus and Aron, stood out against the three \u2018intersecting forms of irresponsibility\u2019\u2014political, moral and intellectual\u2014that \u2018shaped French public life from the end of the First World War until the middle of the 1970s\u2019. Indeed the irresponsibility of French intellectuals had expanded considerably since Past Imperfect, when they had at least, according to Judt, seen themselves as responsible to history, if not to other people. But what did the two contrasting terms actually mean? The Burden of Responsibility provides a distinctly unhelpful tautology, defining \u2018irresponsibility\u2019 as \u2018the propensity in various spheres of public life to neglect or abandon intellectual, moral or political responsibility\u2019. Judt clarifies: \u2018In addition to the qualities of courage and integrity, Blum, Aron, and Camus have something else in common. They were all anti-Communists.\u2019 As the New York Times reviewer of Past Imperfect had laconically remarked, Judt\u2019s idea of a responsible intellectual was simply one whose views he found sympathetic.<\/p>\n

If Judt had no difficulty establishing the \u2018absolute clarity on the Communist question\u2019 of his trio, he systematically downplayed their complicity with imperialism. Yet Blum\u2019s first act, as a chef de cabinet in the 1914 Union Sacr\u00e9e government, was to betray the Socialists\u2019 solemn pre-war promise not to participate in the mutual slaughter of the Great War. In 1925, at the height of the Rif colonial war, he informed the Assembly that there was \u2018not only a right, but a duty for what are known as the superior races to draw towards themselves the races which have not attained the same degree of culture and civilisation\u2019. Becoming Prime Minister again in December 1945, four weeks after the bombardment of Haiphong that launched the French war in Indochina, he explained that the colonial mission of France was \u2018not yet accomplished\u2019. Camus, who said virtually nothing about the war in Indochina, was dismissed even by Aron as no more than \u2018a well-intentioned colonizer\u2019 in Algeria. Both Camus and Aron approved the Anglo-French-Israeli aggression against Egypt in 1956, Aron warning of the \u2018F\u00fchrer on the Nile\u2019 and Camus of the menace of Soviet-backed \u2018Arab imperialism\u2019. Aron himself backed both the French and the American wars in Indochina, and objected to the French war in Algeria not on ethical grounds but because the French civilizing mission, however laudable in itself, \u2018would be unsustainably expensive\u2019. When asked why he never spoke out against French torture in Algeria, Aron replied that he had never known anyone speak in favour of torture, so what was the point? Judt appears to be perfectly satisfied with this example of moral responsibility, whose logic is that the subject need never have been mentioned.<\/p>\n

An allusion to Weber\u2019s classic discussion of the ethics of responsibility illustrated Judt\u2019s tenuous grasp of the complex issues raised by this highly charged term. The \u2018Weberian calculus\u2019, as he glossed it, entailed \u2018the sense that we can behave responsibly without making partisan commitments\u2014or else that a partisan engagement may under certain circumstances be the responsible option\u2019. Weber\u2019s actual view was rather different. For the great sociologist, the ethic of responsibility was embodied by the political actor who took responsibility for the use of \u2018legitimate violence\u2019. He warned, in \u2018Politics as a Vocation\u2019, that \u2018Whomsoever contracts with violent means\u2014and every politician does\u2014is exposed to its specific consequences.\u2019 Ultimately, the political figure faced a choice between one way of using violence and another, without an adequate standard for discriminating between them; to act politically, then, required an absolute belief in the rightness of one\u2019s own cause, in order to transcend the chasm between political ends and means. An ethic of conviction and an ethic of responsibility were not \u2018absolute contrasts, but rather supplements\u2019. Indeed, Weber\u2019s concept of political responsibility here was not far from Sartre\u2019s view, a fact that Judt naturally does not confront. As Sartre put the point, in his long essay in Les Temps modernes following the Hungarian revolution:<\/p>\n

In the worst case, the assumption of a moral position disguises the operation of a politician; in the best it does not affect the facts and the moralist misses the point. But politics, of whatever sort, is an action undertaken in common with certain men against other men.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

Both Sartre and Weber refused the comfortable stance of the moralizer because they were aware of the tension between ethics and politics, and did not try to obscure it with high-sounding bromides.<\/p>\n

3. EUROPE<\/strong><\/p>\n

By the mid-90s the New York Review of Books was offering Judt a more prominent platform, as publicist and commentator, than scholarly work could provide. After his first appearance there in August 1993, reviewing a work on the fate of French Jews under the Vichy regime, Judt became a regular fixture, contributing three or four pieces a year over the next decade. Eventually he would rival, or even overtake, Garton Ash and Buruma in his frequency as a quasi-editorialist, pronouncing not just on France but on Eastern Europe, the lessons of the Cold War and the fate of the West in general. The year 1993 also saw his first contribution to The New Republic: an attack on Althusser, \u2018the Paris strangler\u2019. He would soon join the magazine\u2019s editorial board. The posture Judt had developed in the course of his assaults on the French left\u2014tailing-ending the liberal-establishment vanguard, while portraying himself as a courageous exception, a lone moral voice\u2014served him well within this wider field. In 1995\u201396, as Clinton and Albright elbowed aside Kohl and Mitterrand to knock ex-Yugoslav heads together, Judt lamented the failure of European leadership. In 1997, as the prophets of the Third Way took up residence in Downing Street, he called for a new social-liberal agenda. He lauded Blair\u2019s \u2018firm and honourable stand\u2019 on Kosovo and endorsed the Oslo Accords on Palestine. In The New Republic he contributed to a 1997 \u2018Zionism at 100\u2019 symposium\u2014arguing that Zionism should not be seen as an ethno-nationalist movement, but a universalist-enlightenment one\u2014and attacked Peter Novick\u2019s critique of the instrumentalization of the Judeocide in The Holocaust in American Life.<\/p>\n

In 2008 Judt would publish a selection of these writings in Reappraisals, appointing himself as a memorializer to the contemporary world on the lessons of \u2018the forgotten twentieth century\u2019; such overlooked themes as vigilance against Communism and Holocaust recognition taking pride of place. In his Introduction, Judt regretted that the term \u2018intellectual\u2019 had come to evoke a \u2018narrow band of left-leaning \u201cprogressives\u201d\u2019, with Sartre at their head, rather than his own pantheon: Camus, Koestler and Ko?akowski. Judt\u2019s paean to the last, in keeping with his general approach to the history of ideas, managed to avoid any mention of Ko?akowski\u2019s religious conversion, inconvenient for Judt as a sharp critic of Woytila.<\/p>\n

Unsurprisingly, perhaps, Judt\u2019s historical research took a back seat during this period. His only book between 1993 and 2005 was a slender volume containing three lectures, two of them already published in the NYRB, which appeared as A Grand Illusion? An Essay on Europe in 1996. No rationale was provided for the switch from French socialism to the larger, more nebulous subject of \u2018Europe\u2019 as a historical subject. In his NYRB obituary, Timothy Snyder\u2014demonstrating an astonishing ignorance of his colleague\u2019s actual trajectory\u2014would suggest that it was Judt\u2019s \u2018midlife participation in Eastern European intellectual life, which hastened the break with Marxism [sic] and enabled a more capacious view of the continent.\u2019 But although he liked to term himself an \u2018Eastern Europeanist\u2019, Judt never produced any monograph on the region; even his 1987 \u2018A Politics of Impotence?\u2019 remained a working paper.<\/p>\n

The political tone of A Grand Illusion? was distinctly Euro-pessimist: \u2018a truly united Europe is sufficiently unlikely for it to be unwise and self-defeating to insist on it\u2019. The exceptionally favourable combination of circumstances that drove European integration forward up to the 1980s would not reappear:<\/p>\n

These were unrepeatable, one-time transformations. That is to say, Western Europe will probably never again have to catch up on thirty years of economic stagnation or half a century of agrarian depression, or rebuild after a disastrous war. Nor will it be bound together by the need to do so, or by the coincidence of Communist threat and American encouragement.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

Extension to the East could not occur on the terms granted to existing member states, since this would require huge transfer payments from Western European economies already suffering from persistent unemployment and slow growth. Long-running economic divergences between the two halves of Europe, dating back to before 1914, constituted a major obstacle to unification. Moreover, the lessons of Yugoslavia\u2014this was written at the moment of the Dayton Accords\u2014illustrated \u2018the weakness of European initiatives, the compulsion to avoid engagement and the absence of any recognized collective strategic interest beyond maintaining the status quo\u2019. \u2018In its strong form\u2019, Judt concluded, \u2018the idea of Europe has had its day.\u2019<\/p>\n

Cause c\u00e9l\u00e8bre<\/strong><\/p>\n

At the turn of the century, commentary in the NYRB and New Republic continued to claim much of Judt\u2019s time. His response to 9.11 announced that the world had crossed the threshold into a new moral-political universe. He rallied immediately behind the war in Afghanistan and organized an October 2002 conference on the central war-on-terror theme of \u2018global anti-Americanism\u2019. Like millions of others, however, he was dubious about Bush and Cheney\u2019s plans for the invasion of Iraq; also about the salience of the settlers\u2019 agenda in Israeli politics. In July 2002 he wrote a piece mildly critical of \u2018intolerant, ultra-religious\u2019 settlers and anti-Arab mizrahi Israelis in The New Republic. The following year his NYRB article, \u2018Israel: The Alternative\u2019, created a furore in New York. As Judt would recall, \u2018the rabbis of Riverside\u2019 picketed a talk he was due to give at a local high school, marshalling protesters dressed as concentration-camp inmates. The event says more about the thuggishness of hardline American Zionists than it does about Judt\u2019s essay, which recycled the venerable notion of a bi-national democracy for Israel\u2013Palestine.<\/p>\n

The Oslo process was now over, Judt declared: \u2018Israel continues to mock its American patron, building illegal settlements in general disregard of the \u201croad map\u201d.\u2019 The US president had been \u2018reduced to a ventriloquist\u2019s dummy, pitifully reciting the Israeli cabinet\u2019s line: \u201cIt\u2019s all Arafat\u2019s fault\u201d.\u2019 Palestinian Arabs, \u2018corralled into bantustans\u2019, subsisted on EU handouts. Sharon, Arafat and a handful of terrorists could all \u2018claim victory\u2019. Departing from his previous assertion that Zionism had been a universalist movement, he declared it a typical late-nineteenth-century ethno-nationalist one, and as such an anachronism in \u2018a world that has moved on, a world of individual rights, open frontiers and international law\u2019. Given the demographic trend towards a Palestinian majority in \u2018greater Israel\u2019, the country would now have to choose between being a non-democratic ethno-religious state, with a growing majority of disenfranchised non-Jews, or a multi-cultural, multi-ethnic secular democracy. Israel was already \u2018a multi-cultural society in all but name\u2019, yet ranked its citizens according to ethno-religious criteria. Furthermore, \u2018Israel\u2019s behaviour has been a disaster for American foreign policy\u2019\u2014\u2018Washington\u2019s unconditional support for Israel even in spite of (silent) misgivings is the main reason why most of the world no longer credits our good faith\u2019:<\/p>\n

It is now tacitly conceded by those in a position to know that America\u2019s reasons for going to war in Iraq were not necessarily those advertised at the time. For many in the current US Administration, a major consideration was the need to destabilize and then reconfigure the Middle East in a manner thought favourable to Israel.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

Formerly, the existence of the state of Israel had allowed Jews to \u2018walk tall\u2019. Now, however\u2014the actual tipping-point is not specified\u2014its behaviour left non-Israeli Jews \u2018exposed to criticism and vulnerable to attack for things they didn\u2019t do\u2019\u2014\u2018the depressing truth is that Israel today is bad for the Jews\u2019. The situation had corroded American domestic debate: \u2018Rather than think straight about the Middle East, American politicians and pundits slander our European allies when they dissent, speak glibly and irresponsibly of resurgent anti-Semitism when Israel is criticized and censoriously rebuke any public figure at home who tries to break from the consensus\u2019\u2014Judt apparently forgetting his own censorious rebuke of Novick a few years before. The volte face on Israel led to Judt\u2019s ejection from The New Republic\u2019s editorial board and a rabid riposte from his former friend Leon Wieseltier, its literary editor, who pointed out accurately enough that the idea of a one-state solution, far from requiring anyone to \u2018think the unthinkable\u2019, as Judt had written, was a notion as old as the conflict over Palestine itself.<\/p>\n

Judt did not include the Israel essay in his 2008 collection Reappraisals and seems scarcely to have addressed the one-state solution again. But reckless neo-conservative interventionism and the crudity of right-wing American Zionism had clearly soured him on the society of which he was now a citizen. In early 2005 the NYRB published Judt\u2019s \u2018The Good Society: Europe vs America\u2019, which strongly favoured the former. A few months later Postwar, his 900-page history of Europe since 1945, appeared. The idea of writing on the 1945\u201389 period had apparently come to Judt in December 1989, within a month of the fall of the Berlin Wall: \u2018the history of post-war Europe would need to be rewritten\u2019\u2014in retrospect, the epoch would seem \u2018a post-war parenthesis, the unfinished business of a conflict that ended in 1945 but whose epilogue had lasted for another half century\u2019. In the event, Past Imperfect, A Grand Illusion? and book reviewing had intervened. By the time the book came to be written, Judt\u2019s view of Europe had undergone a dramatic revision.<\/p>\n

Exemplary Europe<\/strong><\/p>\n

For the most part, Postwar offered a familiar narrative of the period, somewhat meandering in structure and largely focused on the West; coverage of Eastern Europe mostly functioned as a sombre counterpoint to the main melody. Opening with a survey of the state of Europe after World War Two, the book covered the onset of Cold War, the advent of western affluence and the \u2018social democratic moment\u2019; the 1960s, East and West; accelerated EEC integration, as a response to 1970s economic turbulence; the new Hayekian \u2018realism\u2019 of the 1980s, in both Thatcherite and mitterrandiste forms; Solidarno??, Gorbachev and the fall of the Comecon regimes in 1989; German reunification, Maastricht, the break-up of Yugoslavia and EU expansion. Into this lengthy, often rather flat account, Judt inserted what he confessed was \u2018an avowedly personal interpretation\u2019. Post-war Europe, he argued, had produced not just the integrated structures of the EU but a social model that stood as a moral \u2018beacon\u2019 to aspirant members and a \u2018global challenge\u2019 to the American way of life. Europe had emerged, at the dawn of the twenty-first century, as a \u2018paragon of the international virtues\u2019:<\/p>\n

a community of values and a system of inter-state relations held up by Europeans and non-Europeans alike as an exemplar for all to emulate. In part this was the backwash of growing disillusion with the American alternative; but the reputation was well earned . . . Neither America nor China had a serviceable model to propose for universal emulation. In spite of the horrors of their recent past\u2014and in large measure because of them\u2014it was Europeans who were now uniquely placed to offer the world some modest advice on how to avoid repeating their own mistakes. Few would have predicted it sixty years before, but the twenty-first century might yet belong to Europe.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

Judt\u2019s argument might be read as a grand narrative for today\u2019s Eurocracy, analogous to the uplifting national tales of the early twentieth century, such as Volpe\u2019s Italia in Cammino or Marshall\u2019s Our Island Story. His aim seems to have been to produce a synthesis of his now-revived admiration for social democracy and his hopes for the EU as an alternative to Bush\u2019s America. The \u2018European social model\u2019 became the new pole of attraction for Judt\u2019s politics: more acceptable than the neo-conservative US and less pass\u00e9 than the labour movement itself. But the attempt to conflate European integration, the post-war welfare state and the record of the social-democratic parties into an exemplar for the twenty-first century ended in analytical incoherence. Postwar oscillated continually between the assertion that \u2018welfare capitalism\u2019 was non-partisan, \u2018truly post-ideological\u2019, and the claim that it was a quintessentially social-democratic creation. On the one hand, the welfare state was the result of a \u2018deep longing for normality\u2019 produced by the inter-war age of extremes and the lessons of World War Two. For the generation of 1945, \u2018some workable balance between political freedoms and the rational, equitable distributive function of the administrative state seemed the only sensible route out of the abyss\u2019. This meant \u2018a broad consensus not to press inherited ideological or cultural divisions to the point of political polarization\u2019 and a \u2018de-politicized citizenry\u2019, capped by \u2018reform-minded\u2019 Christian Democrat parties and \u2018a parliamentary Left\u2019. On the other hand, welfare capitalism was the \u2018distinctive vision\u2019 of social democracy, which held that \u2018genuine improvements in the condition of all classes could be obtained in incremental and peaceful ways\u2019.<\/p>\n

Judt drives home the importance of a social-democratic party to final outcomes by contrasting Scandinavia and Eastern Europe. The reason that Sweden, in particular, did not develop in the same way as \u2018other economically depressed societies on the European margin between the wars\u2019 was due to the Social Democrats. By renouncing \u2018radical dogma and revolutionary ambitions\u2019, the Swedish sad was able to incorporate small-holding peasants and strike a deal with Swedish capital at Saltsj\u00f6baden in 1938. More generally:<\/p>\n

The embittered and destitute peasants of inter-war central and southern Europe formed a ready constituency for Nazis, Fascists or single-issue Agrarian populists. But the equally troubled farmers, loggers, crofters and fishermen of Europe\u2019s far north turned in growing numbers to the Social Democrats, who actively supported agrarian cooperatives . . . and thereby blurred the longstanding socialist distinctions between private production and collectivist goals, \u2018backward\u2019 country and \u2018modern\u2019 town that were so electorally disastrous in other countries.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

The notion of a peasant-based social democracy as the road not taken in inter-war Eastern Europe is, of course, completely unhistorical. Agriculture there was profoundly backward at the time; when popular uprisings weakened landed elites, as happened in Romania, the underlying organization of production tended to revert back to subsistence farming. The agrarian economy simply did not produce adequate surpluses for a sustained modernization drive. This was one reason for the similarity among the modernizing political movements there: liberal, fascist or Communist, all faced the basic problem of extracting sufficient surplus from the peasant sector to industrialize. The choice in Eastern Europe was never really between social democracy and Leninism, but among structurally similar modernizing regimes with different ideological labels. The situation in Scandinavia, particularly in Sweden, was entirely different: a substantial free-holder peasantry existed there, literacy was widespread and agrarian surpluses were much higher. Peasants were never \u2018equally troubled\u2019 in Scandinavia. In general, regional social democracy operated in such a uniquely favourable environment that it was never available as a model for export, as most of its leaders recognized.<\/p>\n

Judt\u2019s argument in Postwar further oscillated between claims that the welfare state has been in serious danger since the 1970s and declarations that it was the cornerstone of the twenty-first-century European social model. The first argument, based on a decidedly sketchy political economy\u2014not a strong suit for Judt, as Postwar showed\u2014claimed that, by the early 1970s, the profit margins that had made the social-democratic class compromise possible came under threat, as the \u2018migration of surplus agricultural labour into productive urban industry\u2019 had ended and \u2018rates of productivity increase began inexorably to decline\u2019; Keynesian stimulus policies created inflation while failing to generate growth. Furthermore, the \u2018white, male, employed working class\u2019, whose social-democratic parties had spearheaded the welfare state, was starting to contract. On the other hand, Judt claimed that it had survived robustly through all the ideological and political din about it. \u2018Economic liberalization did not signal the fall of the welfare state, nor even its terminal decline, notwithstanding the hopes of its theorists. It did, though, illustrate\u2019\u2014strange choice of verb\u2014\u2018a seismic shift in the allocation of resources and initiative from public to private sectors.\u2019<\/p>\n

Postwar\u2019s paean to the European social model stood in striking contrast to the gloomy outlook of A Grand Illusion?, which received no mention. The two books also offered sharply different accounts of Europe\u2019s east\u2013west divide. In 1995, Judt had disputed the notion that the division was \u2018an artificial creation of the Cold War, an iron curtain gratuitously and recently drawn across a single cultural space.\u2019 On the contrary, as early as the fifteenth century there had been \u2018an invisible line that already ran from north to south through the middle of Europe.\u2019 To extend EU membership to the ex-Communist European countries would be \u2018an act of charity\u2019. Without a word of explanation, Postwar reverses these claims: the division is entirely a creation of the Cold War; before World War Two, \u2018the differences between North and South, rich and poor, urban and rural, counted for more than those between East and West.\u2019 After 1945, however:<\/p>\n

The effect of the Sovietization of Eastern Europe was to draw it steadily away from the western half of the continent. Just as Western Europe was about to enter an era of dramatic transformation and unprecedented prosperity, Eastern Europe was slipping into a coma: a winter of inertia and resignation, punctured by cycles of protest and subjugation, that would last for nearly four decades.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

In this reading, the advance of the Soviet glacis had blocked the region\u2019s chance of establishing an indigenous welfare state. Judt\u2019s contrary argument in \u2018Politics of Impotence?\u2019\u2014that central Europeans were so attached to their states\u2019 welfare provisions that they might not look kindly on the restoration of capitalism\u2014had evidently been forgotten.<\/p>\n

Judt\u2019s encomium to the European social model is further undermined by the second, less tendentious strand of his narrative: a rather humdrum account of European integration. As a historian, Judt had little talent for bringing protagonists to life\u2014indeed, little interest in character as such\u2014and Postwar offered no fresh interpretation or archival discoveries. Yet the bare facts it presented on the transnational agreements that eventually produced the EU showed that, whatever one might say about the European social model, it was a historical theme quite independent from that of European union. None of the key stages on the path to integration had much to do with the welfare state; they were mostly the result of geo-political calculations and, from the late 1980s, basically neo-liberal. The 1950 Schuman Plan had allowed Germany to escape from Allied economic controls, while providing a guarantee to the French against German re-armament. As Judt himself pointed out, the European Economic Community was an attempt to open French and German markets, again for largely political reasons. The impetus towards establishing a European monetary system came from an attempt to stabilize exchange rates, after the collapse of the Bretton Woods system. The creation of the European Union, through the 1987 Single European Act and 1992 Maastricht Treaty, established the free circulation of goods, services and capital among its members but also imposed harsh German-style budgetary requirements. As Postwar noted, Eurozone finance ministers would be \u2018unable to respond to the Siren-calls of voters and politicians for easier money and increased public spending\u2019.<\/p>\n

Judt attempted to resolve this tension between the actual dynamics of European integration and his supposed European social model through some implausible rhetorical linkages\u2014for example:<\/p>\n

In relative terms, the so-called \u2018social\u2019 element in the EU budget was tiny\u2014less than 1 percent of gnp. But from the late Eighties, the budgets of the European Community and the Union nevertheless had a distinctively redistributive quality, transferring resources from wealthy regions to poor ones and contributing to a steady reduction in the aggregate gap between rich and poor: substituting in effect, for the nationally based Social-Democratic programmes of an earlier generation.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

This was to confuse wish with reality. Judt himself pointed out twenty pages later that regional and social inequalities in Europe had sharply increased since the 1980s: a small super-rich core now contrasted with the poorer regions of the Mediterranean zone and Eastern Europe. Rather than scaling up a welfarist model, European integration had if anything undermined it.<\/p>\n

What of the \u2018social model\u2019 itself? Judt suggested that, in sharp contrast to the United States, European societies were marked by high taxes, long vacations, free healthcare, good public education and high life expectancy. But the relation between this ideal and actually existing European societies remained unclear. Mostly Judt seemed to be imagining a loose conceptual average of Europe\u2019s rich northwest\u2014Belgium, Denmark, Britain, Ireland, France, Germany, Norway\u2014rather than the uneven social topography of the continent as a whole. Although they were discussed in passing in Postwar, the unequal societies of Europe\u2019s south and east\u2014Portugal, Spain, Italy, GrEECe\u2014were never allowed to impinge on its \u2018social model\u2019. Nor, finally, does Judt\u2019s attempt to counter-pose a \u2018good\u2019 European model to a \u2018bad\u2019 American one stand up. As his own narrative made clear, post-war Europe was closely shaped by US interventionism; Washington took extraordinary measures to reconstruct Western Europe\u2019s economies and to provide its states with a security guarantee that removed the need to rearm. Historically, the \u2018European model\u2019, however specified, has never been an alternative to American hegemony, but rather a consequence of it.<\/p>\n

4. SOCIAL DEMOCRACY?<\/strong><\/p>\n

The fragility of Judt\u2019s attempted synthesis in Postwar was most evident in its rapid breakdown. By the time of his last book, Ill Fares the Land, he had undergone another conversion in political outlook. The book originated as a valedictory lecture at NYU in 2009, given after Judt had been diagnosed with amyotrophic lateral sclerosis. A transcription of the lecture had been published in the NYRB, bringing a \u2018chorus of demands for its expansion into a little book\u2019. The resulting political testament struck a declamatory note: \u2018Something is profoundly wrong with the way we live today\u2019\u2014\u2018and yet we seem unable to conceive of alternatives\u2019. Ill Fares the Land sought to provide one, in the form of a rehabilitated social democracy. Alas for his admirers, the results contradicted or flatly reversed many of Judt\u2019s most confident pronouncements on the welfare state and social democracy in Postwar. The resulting confusion was amply demonstrated in his attempts to grapple with four key questions.<\/p>\n

(i) The welfare state\u2014who created it?<\/strong><\/p>\n

Judt wanted to maintain once again that the welfare state was both the product of a cross-party \u2018Keynesian consensus\u2019 and a historic social-democratic achievement. But whereas Postwar had celebrated the superiority of Europe\u2019s social model, Ill Fares the Land played down any such contrast, arguing instead that Roosevelt\u2019s New Deal and Johnson\u2019s Great Society were in practice the American version of social democracy. The \u2018longing for normality\u2019 after World War Two that had explained Europeans\u2019 special predilection for state-administered welfare in Postwar now apparently applied to Americans as well. A continual slippage in Judt\u2019s use of the term \u2018social democracy\u2019 sometimes allowed it to suggest a form of Hegelian historical reason, an \u2018objective\u2019 purpose that escapes the \u2018subjective\u2019 intentions of those involved. Thus anyone who supported post-war Keynesian demand management gets promoted to the rank of \u2018objective\u2019 social democrat\u2014and larded with praise\u2014whatever his or her party label:<\/p>\n

Not only did social democrats sustain full employment for nearly three decades, they also maintained growth rates more than competitive with those of the untrammelled market economies of the past. And on the back of these economic successes they introduced radically disjunctive social changes that came to seem, within a short span of years, quite normal. When Lyndon Johnson spoke of building a \u2018great society\u2019 on the basis of massive public expenditure on a variety of government-sponsored programs and agencies, few objected and fewer still thought the proposition odd.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

Supporters of Eugene McCarthy\u2014indeed, LBJ himself\u2014might be surprised at this retrospective elevation to the status of a Yankee Olof Palme.<\/p>\n

Similarly, while Postwar had given pride of place to Scandinavian and British social democracy, Ill Fares the Land explained that \u2018pure\u2019 social democracy along Scandinavian lines had always been \u2018non-exportable\u2019, while the welfare state created by post-war British Labour was not really social democratic at all, but simply \u2018pragmatic\u2019. Accompanying this was a much more pronounced emphasis on the non-radicalism of the welfare state, now not just \u2018post-ideological\u2019, as in Postwar, but the creation of \u2018instinctive conservatives\u2019. By Judt\u2019s criteria, indeed, Berlusconi, Sarkozy and Merkel might count as social democrats:<\/p>\n

Social democracy, in one form or another, is the prose of contemporary European politics. There are very few European politicians, and fewer still in positions of influence, who would dissent from core social democratic assumptions about the duties of the state, however much they might differ as to their scope.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

The conceptual muddiness of this approach, in which virtually all political actors become the unwitting instruments of a social-democratic Geist, succeeds only in obscuring the central political and historical issues: what was the actual role of social-democratic parties in the construction of the welfare state, and what part was played by broader political-economic conditions? These were questions that Judt never even posed. Two essential components to any answer might be stressed, though: firstly, the long economic boom of the post-war period, which has little if any linkage to the strength of social-democratic parties but whose arc tracks the expansion of welfarism very closely. Secondly, the existence of a rival Communist bloc, proclaiming itself the homeland of the workers. The conversion of social-democratic parties into neo-liberal centre lefts followed the decline and fall of the state-socialist challenge. Judt, the life-long anti-Communist, at one point lets this slip himself:<\/p>\n

That is why the fall of Communism mattered so much. With its collapse, there unravelled the whole skein of doctrines that had bound the Left together for over a century. However perverted the Muscovite variation, its sudden and complete disappearance could not but have a disruptive impact on any party or movement calling itself \u2018social democratic\u2019 . . . for the Left, the absence of a historically buttressed narrative leaves an empty space.<\/p><\/blockquote>\n

However one defines the relationship, empirically it seems clear that social democracy has been deeply dependent on its revolutionary twin. The attempt to formulate a social-democratic politics in the absence of a socialist one would seem historically implausible.<\/p>\n

(ii) The welfare state\u2014what went wrong?<\/strong><\/p>\n

Without explanation, the boosterism of Postwar, in which the European social model had been a beacon to the world, turned to cassandrism in Ill Fares the Land, which saw the welfare state as disastrously eroded by rising inequality and declining public services. Judt focused chiefly on the US and UK, but made clear that not even Sweden, France, Germany or the Netherlands had been exempt from negative developments. What explained this deterioration? Principally, Judt argued, it was the fault of the generation that had grown up under the post-war welfare state and had taken the security it gave them for granted, becoming disaffected instead of grateful: \u2018the narcissism of the student movements, new Left ideologues and the popular culture of the 60s generation invited a conservative backlash\u2019, allowing the Right to roll forward the \u2018intellectual revolution\u2019 mounted by Hayek and Friedman, imposing a free-market dogmatics on the political scene\u2014an outcome that was \u2018far from inevitable\u2019.<\/p>\n

For Judt, the crisis of the welfare state was therefore largely a matter of ideas\u2014selfish ones on the part of the 60s radicals, and counter-arguments that were \u2018forceful indeed\u2019 from the Hayekians. If things had been otherwise, the post-war consensus would presumably still be intact. What was striking was the complete absence of any economic explanation of the crisis in the \u2018Keynesian consensus\u2019 around Judt\u2019s welfare state. Where economic changes received any mention, it was always as an aside. Thus: \u2018As the post-war boom wound down\u2019\u2014no explanation of why it did so\u2014unemployment rose and the tax-base of the state was threatened. Or: \u2018Only when the welfare state began to run into difficulties\u2019\u2014unexplained\u2014did neo-liberal ideas take hold. Or: \u2018The growth in unemployment over the course of the 1970s\u2019 and \u2018the inflation of those years\u2019\u2014unexplained\u2014put new strains on the exchequer. Although the crisis of welfarism was the central topic in Ill Fares the Land, there was even less material explanation of it than in Postwar.<\/p>\n

(iii) Social Democracy: success or failure?<\/strong><\/p>\n

Overlapping with Judt\u2019s account of welfarism was his depiction of the fate of social democracy, tacitly understood as parties of the Socialist International. Were they the vehicle for a renewed welfare state? Judt mentioned in passing a variety of partly contradictory causes for their \u2018loss of nerve\u2019: a shrinking working class; the fall of Communism; the fact that social democracy \u2018in one form or another\u2019 had become so generalized\u2014\u2018the prose of contemporary European politics\u2019, as above\u2014that the parties themselves now had little distinctive to offer. But Judt could not afford to let such gloomy reflections go too far, lest they undermine the purpose of his book\u2014a ringing call to revive social democracy as the last best hope of the age. The resulting sermon contradicted itself at every step. Thus, by the end of the twentieth century, social democracy had not merely \u2018fulfilled many of its long-standing objectives\u2019, but \u2018succeeded beyond the wildest dreams of its founders\u2019\u2014though presumably Judt was not here referring to Marx, Engels, Bebel, Bernstein. Yet in that case, why was the land faring so ill? Or again: a \u2018defensive stance made sense\u2019 for social democracy, to \u2018convince voters that it was a respectable radical choice within a liberal polity\u2019. Yet \u2018social democracy cannot just be about preserving worthy institutions as a defence against worse options\u2019.<\/p>\n

(iv) What is to be done?<\/strong><\/p>\n

Success or failure, however, for the moment social democracy had \u2018lost its way\u2019. What was needed to put it back on the right track? Judt\u2019s answer was a ne plus ultra of vapid idealism: it was a better kind of language that would change the world. For the problem of contemporary social democracy was \u2018not what to do\u2019 [sic] but \u2018how to talk about it\u2019\u2014\u2018our disability is discursive: we simply do not know how to talk about these things any more\u2019. Ill Fares the Land harped on this theme from the start, as Judt pondered how to answer a twelve-year-old who had warned him that the word \u2018socialism\u2019 was toxic in the us; Judt\u2019s solution was to tell the boy to forget \u2018socialism\u2019 and think instead of \u2018social democracy\u2019, with its wholesome \u2018acceptance of capitalism\u2019.<\/p>\n

A \u2018new language of politics\u2019 was, of course, the thesis of Furet\u2019s Rethinking the French Revolution, in which society more or less levitated by the sheer magic of words. But Judt gave a characteristically British twist to this French conception: the discourse that would rescue social democracy was a \u2018moral narrative\u2019, though Judt did not explain what such a narrative might say. Combined with this was a call to rehabilitate the state, as \u2018the only institution standing between individuals and non-state actors like banks or international corporations\u2019\u2014though since Judt did not specify what the state should do, the effect was little more than rhetorical. Judt was, of course, very ill at the time. Nevertheless, it boggles the mind to think that a serious observer of current affairs living in the United States could in 2010 describe the \u2018state\u2019 as a neutral third party, standing between banks and individuals. This was the political order that socialized the massive bank losses of 2008 against widespread popular rage. The discontinuity of style and personnel between Bush and Obama has only underscored the fundamental continuity of state policy toward the banks. Ill Fares the Land concluded with a desperately bland set of political prescriptions. \u2018Incremental improvements upon unsatisfactory circumstances are the best we can hope for, and all we should seek.\u2019 With full allowance made for the conditions in which he was working at this stage\u2014the nightmare of his advancing paralysis vividly described in the pages of the NYRB \u2014in Judt\u2019s final testament, neo-social democracy remains remarkably insipid.<\/p>\n

Assessment<\/strong><\/p>\n

How do the accolades for Judt as a \u2018great historian\u2019, \u2018fearless critic\u2019 and \u2018brilliant political commentator\u2019 stand up against a cool examination of his work? As historiography, even his earliest, most substantial scholarly works on France\u2014Reconstruction of the Socialist Party and Socialism in Provence\u2014were weakened by the aggressive tendentiousness of his approach. Marxism and the French Left and Past Imperfect were avowedly selective and polemical. Judt lacked the most basic requirement for any student of intellectual history: the ability to grasp and reconstruct an idea with philological precision. His lack of interest in ideas is borne out in extenso throughout his copious writings on intellectuals: there were never any serious attempts to reconstruct a thinker\u2019s position, so as to probe and question it. Even summaries of figures to whom he was well-disposed were slapdash; writers to whom he was hostile were regularly excoriated for views they did not hold. Judged as an intellectual historian, the verdict on Judt must be negative. His magnum opus, Postwar, is regularly listed for undergraduate European History courses. But its 900 pages produced little new by way of evidence or interpretation\u2014a weakness underlined by the absence of even the most minimal scholarly apparatus, beyond a \u2018general bibliography\u2019 available from NYU.<\/p>\n

Judt himself confessed in his final interview that at school he had been considered \u2018better at literature than history\u2019; also bragging, \u2018I was\u2014and knew I was\u2014among the best speakers and writers of my age cohort. I don\u2019t mean I was the best historian\u2019. In effect, it was his talent, limited but real, as a polemicist and a pamphleteer that disqualified Judt as a historian of ideas, much as he liked to claim the loftier calling. His range as a polemicist was relatively narrow: there is a limit to what can be got from attacking the French left or lauding fellow defenders of the Free World. His negative judgements on political leaders\u2014Thatcher, Bush, Clinton, Blair\u2014carried little analytical heft; his belated criticism of Israel\u2019s West Bank settlements never explained at what point the Zionist project had gone wrong. Nevertheless, judged as a polemicist, the verdict can be more favourable, exonerating Judt of the heedless inconsistencies, both conceptual and analytic, that marred his work as historian of Europe and latter-day champion of neo-social democracy. A pamphleteer may be allowed\u2014even expected\u2014to change his views more or less at the drop of a hat. If the EU is now a moral beacon to the world, now a sad example of failed leadership; or the welfare state now the legacy of organized labour, now the common sense of capitalist politicians\u2014so what? All grist to the mill. A historian will be held to different standards.<\/p>\n","protected":false},"excerpt":{"rendered":"

The Article: Tony Judt: A Cooler Look by Dylan Riley in the New Left Review. The Text: Accolades continue to be piled upon the historian Tony Judt, following his untimely death in August 2010. For the Guardian, he was \u2018a fearless critic of narrow orthodoxies\u2019, \u2018a great historian\u2019, \u2018a brilliant political commentator\u2019. For the New […]<\/p>\n","protected":false},"author":49,"featured_media":0,"comment_status":"open","ping_status":"closed","sticky":false,"template":"","format":"standard","meta":{"footnotes":""},"categories":[259],"tags":[],"yoast_head":"\nExamining The Legacy Of Tony Judt - Prose Before Hos<\/title>\n<meta name=\"description\" content=\"The Article: Tony Judt: A Cooler Look by Dylan Riley in the New Left Review. The Text: Accolades continue to be piled upon the historian Tony Judt,\" \/>\n<meta name=\"robots\" content=\"index, follow, max-snippet:-1, max-image-preview:large, max-video-preview:-1\" \/>\n<link rel=\"canonical\" href=\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/\" \/>\n<meta property=\"og:locale\" content=\"en_US\" \/>\n<meta property=\"og:type\" content=\"article\" \/>\n<meta property=\"og:title\" content=\"Examining The Legacy Of Tony Judt - Prose Before Hos\" \/>\n<meta property=\"og:description\" content=\"The Article: Tony Judt: A Cooler Look by Dylan Riley in the New Left Review. The Text: Accolades continue to be piled upon the historian Tony Judt,\" \/>\n<meta property=\"og:url\" content=\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/\" \/>\n<meta property=\"og:site_name\" content=\"Prose Before Hos\" \/>\n<meta property=\"article:published_time\" content=\"2011-10-21T20:26:51+00:00\" \/>\n<meta property=\"article:modified_time\" content=\"2012-12-26T21:08:04+00:00\" \/>\n<meta name=\"author\" content=\"Article of the Day\" \/>\n<meta name=\"twitter:card\" content=\"summary_large_image\" \/>\n<meta name=\"twitter:creator\" content=\"@pbhnetwork\" \/>\n<meta name=\"twitter:site\" content=\"@pbhnetwork\" \/>\n<meta name=\"twitter:label1\" content=\"Written by\" \/>\n\t<meta name=\"twitter:data1\" content=\"Article of the Day\" \/>\n\t<meta name=\"twitter:label2\" content=\"Est. reading time\" \/>\n\t<meta name=\"twitter:data2\" content=\"57 minutes\" \/>\n<script type=\"application\/ld+json\" class=\"yoast-schema-graph\">{\"@context\":\"https:\/\/schema.org\",\"@graph\":[{\"@type\":\"WebPage\",\"@id\":\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/\",\"url\":\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/\",\"name\":\"Examining The Legacy Of Tony Judt - Prose Before Hos\",\"isPartOf\":{\"@id\":\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/#website\"},\"datePublished\":\"2011-10-21T20:26:51+00:00\",\"dateModified\":\"2012-12-26T21:08:04+00:00\",\"author\":{\"@id\":\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/#\/schema\/person\/1e19d7cf2b1a9aea1805fd7b4b4b2b4e\"},\"description\":\"The Article: Tony Judt: A Cooler Look by Dylan Riley in the New Left Review. The Text: Accolades continue to be piled upon the historian Tony Judt,\",\"breadcrumb\":{\"@id\":\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/#breadcrumb\"},\"inLanguage\":\"en-US\",\"potentialAction\":[{\"@type\":\"ReadAction\",\"target\":[\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/\"]}]},{\"@type\":\"BreadcrumbList\",\"@id\":\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/#breadcrumb\",\"itemListElement\":[{\"@type\":\"ListItem\",\"position\":1,\"name\":\"Home\",\"item\":\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/\"},{\"@type\":\"ListItem\",\"position\":2,\"name\":\"Examining The Legacy Of Tony Judt\"}]},{\"@type\":\"WebSite\",\"@id\":\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/#website\",\"url\":\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/\",\"name\":\"Prose Before Hos\",\"description\":\"The Far Side Of Politics\",\"potentialAction\":[{\"@type\":\"SearchAction\",\"target\":{\"@type\":\"EntryPoint\",\"urlTemplate\":\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/?s={search_term_string}\"},\"query-input\":\"required name=search_term_string\"}],\"inLanguage\":\"en-US\"},{\"@type\":\"Person\",\"@id\":\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/#\/schema\/person\/1e19d7cf2b1a9aea1805fd7b4b4b2b4e\",\"name\":\"Article of the Day\",\"sameAs\":[\"https:\/\/twitter.com\/pbhnetwork\"],\"url\":\"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/author\/article-of-the-day\/\"}]}<\/script>\n<!-- \/ Yoast SEO plugin. -->","yoast_head_json":{"title":"Examining The Legacy Of Tony Judt - Prose Before Hos","description":"The Article: Tony Judt: A Cooler Look by Dylan Riley in the New Left Review. The Text: Accolades continue to be piled upon the historian Tony Judt,","robots":{"index":"index","follow":"follow","max-snippet":"max-snippet:-1","max-image-preview":"max-image-preview:large","max-video-preview":"max-video-preview:-1"},"canonical":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/","og_locale":"en_US","og_type":"article","og_title":"Examining The Legacy Of Tony Judt - Prose Before Hos","og_description":"The Article: Tony Judt: A Cooler Look by Dylan Riley in the New Left Review. The Text: Accolades continue to be piled upon the historian Tony Judt,","og_url":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/","og_site_name":"Prose Before Hos","article_published_time":"2011-10-21T20:26:51+00:00","article_modified_time":"2012-12-26T21:08:04+00:00","author":"Article of the Day","twitter_card":"summary_large_image","twitter_creator":"@pbhnetwork","twitter_site":"@pbhnetwork","twitter_misc":{"Written by":"Article of the Day","Est. reading time":"57 minutes"},"schema":{"@context":"https:\/\/schema.org","@graph":[{"@type":"WebPage","@id":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/","url":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/","name":"Examining The Legacy Of Tony Judt - Prose Before Hos","isPartOf":{"@id":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/#website"},"datePublished":"2011-10-21T20:26:51+00:00","dateModified":"2012-12-26T21:08:04+00:00","author":{"@id":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/#\/schema\/person\/1e19d7cf2b1a9aea1805fd7b4b4b2b4e"},"description":"The Article: Tony Judt: A Cooler Look by Dylan Riley in the New Left Review. The Text: Accolades continue to be piled upon the historian Tony Judt,","breadcrumb":{"@id":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/#breadcrumb"},"inLanguage":"en-US","potentialAction":[{"@type":"ReadAction","target":["https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/"]}]},{"@type":"BreadcrumbList","@id":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/article-of-the-day\/10\/21\/examining-the-legacy-of-tony-judt\/#breadcrumb","itemListElement":[{"@type":"ListItem","position":1,"name":"Home","item":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/"},{"@type":"ListItem","position":2,"name":"Examining The Legacy Of Tony Judt"}]},{"@type":"WebSite","@id":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/#website","url":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/","name":"Prose Before Hos","description":"The Far Side Of Politics","potentialAction":[{"@type":"SearchAction","target":{"@type":"EntryPoint","urlTemplate":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/?s={search_term_string}"},"query-input":"required name=search_term_string"}],"inLanguage":"en-US"},{"@type":"Person","@id":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/#\/schema\/person\/1e19d7cf2b1a9aea1805fd7b4b4b2b4e","name":"Article of the Day","sameAs":["https:\/\/twitter.com\/pbhnetwork"],"url":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/author\/article-of-the-day\/"}]}},"_links":{"self":[{"href":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/9015"}],"collection":[{"href":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts"}],"about":[{"href":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/types\/post"}],"author":[{"embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/users\/49"}],"replies":[{"embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/comments?post=9015"}],"version-history":[{"count":1,"href":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/9015\/revisions"}],"predecessor-version":[{"id":133780,"href":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/9015\/revisions\/133780"}],"wp:attachment":[{"href":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/media?parent=9015"}],"wp:term":[{"taxonomy":"category","embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/categories?post=9015"},{"taxonomy":"post_tag","embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/www.prosebeforehos.com\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/tags?post=9015"}],"curies":[{"name":"wp","href":"https:\/\/api.w.org\/{rel}","templated":true}]}}